-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 0
/
Copy pathchap-1.2.tex
516 lines (454 loc) · 18.5 KB
/
chap-1.2.tex
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
\section{Induction}
\label{Induction}
\index{induction|(}%
In the section, we consider several induction principles, i.e.,
methods for proving that every element $x$ of some set $A$ has a
property $P(x)$.
\subsection{Mathematical Induction}
We begin with the familiar principle of mathematical induction,
which is a basic result of set theory.
\index{mathematical induction}%
\index{induction!mathematical|see{mathematical induction}}%
\begin{theorem}[Principle of Mathematical Induction]
Suppose $P(n)$ is a property of a natural number $n$.
If
\begin{description}
\item[\quad(basis step)]
\begin{gather*}
P(0) \eqtxtl{and}
\end{gather*}
\item[\quad(inductive step)]
\begin{gather*}
\eqtxtr{for all}n\in\nats,
\eqtxt{if}\eqtxt{\rm(\dag)} P(n),\eqtxt{then}P(n+1),
\end{gather*}
\end{description}
then,
\begin{gather*}
\eqtxtr{for all}n\in\nats,\,P(n) .
\end{gather*}
\end{theorem}
We refer to the formula (\dag) as the \emph{inductive hypothesis}.
\index{inductive hypothesis!mathematical induction}%
\index{mathematical induction!inductive hypothesis}%
To use the principle to show that that every natural
number has property $P$, we carry out two steps. In the basis step,
we show that $0$ has property $P$. In the inductive step, we
assume that $n$ is a natural number with property $P$. We then show
that $n+1$ has property $P$, without making any more assumptions about
$n$.
Next we give an example of a mathematical induction.
\begin{proposition}
\label{MathIndExamp}
For all $n\in\nats$, $3n^2 + 3n + 6$ is divisible by $6$.
\end{proposition}
\begin{proof}
We proceed by mathematical induction.
\begin{description}
\item[\quad(Basis Step)] We have that
$3\cdot 0^2 + 3\cdot 0 + 6 = 0 + 0 + 6 = 6 = 6\cdot 1$. Thus
$3\cdot 0^2 + 3\cdot 0 + 6$ is divisible by $6$.
\item[\quad(Inductive Step)] Suppose $n\in\nats$, and assume the
inductive hypothesis: $3n^2 + 3n + 6$ is divisible by $6$.
Hence $3n^2 + 3n + 6$ = $6m$, for some $m\in\nats$.
Thus, we have that
\begin{align*}
3(n + 1)^2 + 3(n + 1) + 6
&= 3(n^2 + 2n + 1) + 3n + 3 + 6 \\
&= 3n^2 + 6n + 3 + 3n + 3 + 6 \\
&= (3n^2 + 3n + 6) + (6n + 6) \\
&= 6m + 6(n + 1) \\
&= 6(m + (n + 1)) ,
\end{align*}
showing that $3(n + 1)^2 + 3(n + 1) + 6$ is divisible by $6$.
\end{description}
\end{proof}
\begin{exercise}
Use Proposition~\ref{MathIndExamp} to prove, by mathematical induction,
that, for all $n\in\nats$, $n(n^2 + 5)$ is divisible by $6$.
\end{exercise}
\subsection{Strong Induction}
Next, we consider the principle of strong induction.
\index{strong induction}%
\index{induction!strong|see{strong induction}}%
\begin{theorem}[Principle of Strong Induction]
Suppose $P(n)$ is a property of a natural number $n$.
If
\begin{ctabbing}
for all $n\in\nats$, \\
if {\rm(\dag)} for all $m\in\nats$, if $m<n$, then $P(m)$, \\
then $P(n)$,
\end{ctabbing}
then
\begin{gather*}
\eqtxtr{for all}n\in\nats,\,P(n) .
\end{gather*}
\end{theorem}
We refer to the formula (\dag) as the \emph{inductive hypothesis}.
\index{inductive hypothesis!strong induction}%
\index{strong induction!inductive hypothesis}%
To use the principle to show that every natural number has property
$P$, we assume that $n$ is a natural number, and that
every natural number that is strictly smaller than $n$ has
property $P$. We then show that $n$ has property $P$,
without making any more assumptions about $n$.
It turns out that we can use mathematical induction to prove the
validity of the principle of strong induction, by using a property
$Q(n)$ derived from $P(n)$.
\begin{proof}
Suppose $P(n)$ is a property, and assume
\begin{ctabbing}
(\ddag) \=\+ for all $n\in\nats$, \\
if for all $m\in\nats$, if $m<n$, then $P(m)$, \\
then $P(n)$.
\end{ctabbing}
Let the property $Q(n)$ be
\begin{center}
for all $m\in\nats$, if $m<n$, then $P(m)$.
\end{center}
First, we use mathematical induction to show that, for all
$n\in\nats$, $Q(n)$.
\begin{description}
\item[\quad(Basis Step)] We must show $Q(0)$.
Suppose $m\in\nats$ and $m<0$. We must show
that $P(m)$. Since $m<0$ is a contradiction,
\index{contradiction}%
we are allowed to conclude anything. So, we conclude $P(m)$.
\item[\quad(Inductive Step)] Suppose $n\in\nats$, and assume
the inductive hypothesis: $Q(n)$. We must show that $Q(n+1)$.
Suppose $m\in\nats$ and $m<n+1$. We must show that
$P(m)$. Since $m\leq n$, there are two cases to consider.
\begin{itemize}
\item Suppose $m<n$. Because $Q(n)$, we have
that $P(m)$.
\item Suppose $m=n$. We must show that $P(n)$.
By Property~(\ddag), it will suffice to show that
\begin{center}
for all $m\in\nats$, if $m<n$, then $P(m)$.
\end{center}
But this formula is exactly $Q(n)$, and so were are done.
\end{itemize}
\end{description}
Now, we use the result of our mathematical induction to show that, for
all $n\in\nats$, $P(n)$. Suppose $n\in\nats$. By our mathematical
induction, we have $Q(n)$. By Property~(\ddag), it will suffice to show
that
\begin{center}
for all $m\in\nats$, if $m<n$, then $P(m)$.
\end{center}
But this formula is exactly $Q(n)$, and so we are done.
\end{proof}
As an example use of the principle of strong induction, we
will prove a proposition that we would normally take for granted:
\begin{proposition}
\label{NonemptyLeastProp}
Every nonempty set of natural numbers has a least element.
\end{proposition}
\begin{proof}
Let $X$ be a nonempty set of natural numbers.
We begin by using strong induction to show that, for all $n\in\nats$,
\begin{gather*}
\eqtxtr{if}n\in X,\eqtxt{then}X\eqtxtl{has a least element}.
\end{gather*}
Suppose $n\in\nats$, and assume the inductive hypothesis:
for all $m\in\nats$, if $m<n$, then
\begin{gather*}
\eqtxtr{if}m\in X,\eqtxt{then}X\eqtxtl{has a least element}.
\end{gather*}
We must show that
\begin{gather*}
\eqtxtr{if}n\in X,\eqtxt{then}X\eqtxtl{has a least element}.
\end{gather*}
Suppose $n\in X$. It remains to show that $X$ has a least element.
If $n$ is less-than-or-equal-to every element of $X$, then we are
done. Otherwise, there is an $m\in X$ such that $m<n$.
By the inductive hypothesis, we have that
\begin{gather*}
\eqtxtr{if}m\in X,\eqtxt{then}X\eqtxtl{has a least element}.
\end{gather*}
But $m\in X$, and thus $X$ has a least element. This completes our
strong induction.
Now we use the result of our strong induction to prove that $X$ has a
least element. Since $X$ is a nonempty subset of $\nats$, there is an
$n\in\nats$ such that $n\in X$. By the result of our induction, we
can conclude that
\begin{gather*}
\eqtxtr{if}n\in X,\eqtxt{then}X\eqtxtl{has a least element}.
\end{gather*}
But $n\in X$, and thus $X$ has a least element.
\end{proof}
We conclude this subsection with one more proof using strong
induction. Recall that a natural number is prime iff it
is at least $2$ and has no divisors other than $1$ and itself.
\begin{proposition}
For all $n\in\nats$,
\begin{displaymath}
\eqtxtr{if}n\geq 2,
\eqtxtr{then there are}m,l\in\nats\eqtxt{such that}n=ml\eqtxt{and}m
\eqtxtl{is prime.}
\end{displaymath}
\end{proposition}
\begin{proof}
We proceed by strong induction. Suppose $n\in\nats$, and assume the
inductive hypothesis: for all $i\in\nats$, if $i<n$, then
\begin{displaymath}
\eqtxtr{if}i\geq 2,
\eqtxtr{then there are}m,l\in\nats\eqtxt{such that}i=ml\eqtxt{and}m
\eqtxtl{is prime.}
\end{displaymath}
We must show that
\begin{displaymath}
\eqtxtr{if}n\geq 2,
\eqtxtr{then there are}m,l\in\nats\eqtxt{such that}n=ml\eqtxt{and}m
\eqtxtl{is prime.}
\end{displaymath}
Suppose $n\geq 2$. We must show that
\begin{displaymath}
\eqtxtr{there are}m,l\in\nats\eqtxt{such that}n=ml\eqtxt{and}m
\eqtxtl{is prime.}
\end{displaymath}
There are two cases to consider.
\begin{itemize}
\item Suppose $n$ is prime. Then $n,1\in\nats$, $n=n1$ and $n$ is prime.
\item Suppose $n$ is not prime. Since $n\geq 2$, it follows that $n=ij$ for
some $i,j\in\nats$ such that $1<i<n$. Thus, by the inductive
hypothesis, we have that
\begin{displaymath}
\eqtxtr{if}i\geq 2,
\eqtxtr{then there are}m,l\in\nats\eqtxt{such that}i=ml\eqtxt{and}m
\eqtxtl{is prime.}
\end{displaymath}
But $i\geq 2$, and thus there are $m,l\in\nats$ such that
$i=ml$ and $m$ is prime.
Thus $m,lj\in\nats$, $n=ij=(ml)j=m(lj)$ and $m$ is prime.
\end{itemize}
\end{proof}
\begin{exercise}
Use strong induction to prove that, for all $n\in\nats$, if
$n\geq 1$, then there are $i,j\in\nats$ such that $n=2^i(2j + 1)$.
\end{exercise}
\subsection{Well-founded Induction}
We can also do induction over a well-founded relation. A relation $R$
on a set $A$ is \emph{well-founded} iff every nonempty subset $X$ of
\index{relation!well-founded}%
\index{well-founded relation}%
$A$ has an $R$-minimal element, where an element $x\in X$ is
$R$-\emph{minimal in} $X$ iff
\index{relation!well-founded!minimal@$R$-eqtxt{minimal}}%
\index{well-founded relation!minimal@$R$-eqtxt{minimal}}%
there is no $y\in X$ such that $y\mathrel{R}x$.
Given a relation $R$ on a set $A$, and $x,y\in A$, we say that $y$
\emph{is a predecessor
\index{relation!well-founded!predecessor}%
\index{well-founded relation!predecessor}%
\index{predecessor}%
of} $x$ \emph{in} $R$ iff $y\mathrel{R}x$. Thus $x\in X$ is
$R$-minimal in $X$ iff none of $x$'s predecessors in $R$ (there may
be none) are in $X$.
For example, in Proposition~\ref{NonemptyLeastProp}, we proved that
the strict total ordering $<$ on $\nats$ is well-founded. On the other hand,
the strict total ordering $<$ on $\ints$ is \emph{not} well-founded, as $\ints$
itself lacks a $<$-minimal element.
Here's another negative example, showing that even if the underlying
set is finite, the relation need not be well-founded. Let
$A = \{0,1\}$, and $R = \{(0,1), (1,0)\}$. Then $0$ is the only
predecessor of $1$ in $R$, and $1$ is the only predecessor of $0$ in
$R$. Of the nonempty subsets of $A$, we have that $\{0\}$ and $\{1\}$
have $R$-minimal elements. But consider $A$ itself. Then $0$ is not
$R$-minimal in $A$, because $1\in A$ and $1\mathrel{R}0$. And $1$ is
not $R$-minimal in $A$, because $0\in A$ and $0\mathrel{R}1$. Hence
$R$ is not well-founded.
\index{well-founded induction}%
\index{induction!well-founded|see{well-founded induction}}%
\begin{theorem}[Principle of Well-founded Induction]
Suppose $A$ is a set, $R$ is a well-founded relation on $A$, and
$P(x)$ is a property of an element $x\in A$.
If
\begin{ctabbing}
for all $x\in A$, \\
if {\rm(\dag)} for all $y\in A$, if $y\mathrel{R}x$, then $P(y)$, \\
then $P(x)$,
\end{ctabbing}
then
\begin{gather*}
\eqtxtr{for all}x\in A,\,P(x) .
\end{gather*}
\end{theorem}
We refer to the formula (\dag) as the \emph{inductive hypothesis}.
\index{inductive hypothesis!well-founded induction}%
\index{well-founded induction!inductive hypothesis}%
When $A=\nats$ and $R={<}$, this is the same as the principle
of strong induction. But it's much more generally applicable than
strong induction. Furthermore, the proof of this theorem isn't
by induction.
\begin{proof}
Suppose $A$ is a set, $R$ is a well-founded relation on $A$,
$P(x)$ is a property of an element $x\in A$, and
\begin{ctabbing}
(\ddag) \=\+ for all $x\in A$, \\
if for all $y\in A$, if $y\mathrel{R}x$, then $P(y)$, \\
then $P(x)$.
\end{ctabbing}
We must show that, for all $x\in A$, $P(x)$.
Suppose, toward a contradiction, that it is not the case
that, for all $x\in A$, $P(x)$. Hence there is an $x\in A$ such
that $P(x)$ is false.
Let $X=\setof{x\in A}{P(x)\eqtxtl{is false}}$. Thus
$x\in X$, showing that $X$ is non-empty.
Because $R$ is well-founded on $A$, it follows that there is a $z\in X$
that is $R$-minimal in $X$, i.e., such that there is no $y\in X$ such that
$y\mathrel{R}z$.
By (\ddag) and since $z\in X\sub A$, we have that
\begin{ctabbing}
if for all $y\in A$, if $y\mathrel{R}z$, then $P(y)$, \\
then $P(z)$.
\end{ctabbing}
Because $z\in X$, we have that $P(z)$ is false.
Thus, to obtain a contradiction, it will suffice to
show that
\begin{ctabbing}
for all $y\in A$, if $y\mathrel{R}z$, then $P(y)$.
\end{ctabbing}
Suppose $y\in A$, and $y\mathrel{R}z$. We must show that $P(y)$.
Because $z$ is $R$-minimal in $X$, it follows that $y\not\in X$.
Thus $P(y)$.
Because we obtained our contradiction, we have that,
for all $x\in A$, $P(x)$, as required.
\end{proof}
We conclude this subsection by considering three ways of building
well-founded relations. The first is by taking a subset of
a well-founded relation:
\begin{proposition}
\label{WellFoundedSubset}
Suppose $R$ is a well-founded relation on a set $A$. If $S\sub R$,
then $S$ is also a well-founded relation on $A$.
\end{proposition}
\begin{proof}
Suppose $R$ is a well-founded relation on $A$, and $S\sub R$. Let
$X$ be a nonempty subset of $A$. Let $x\in X$ be $R$-minimal in $X$.
Suppose, toward a contradiction, that $x$ is not $S$-minimal in $X$.
Thus there is a $y\in X$ such that $y\mathrel{S}x$. But $S\sub R$,
and thus $y\mathrel{R}x$---contradiction. Thus $x$ is $S$-minimal
in $X$, as required.
\end{proof}
Let the \emph{predecessor} relation $\pred_\nats$ on $\nats$ be
$\setof{(n,n+1)}{n\in\nats}$.
\index{relation!well-founded!predecessor relation}%
\index{well-founded relation!predecessor relation}%
\index{predecessor relation}%
\index{relation!well-founded!predecessor@$\pred_\nats$}%
\index{well-founded relation!predecessor@$\pred_\nats$}%
\index{predecessor@$\pred_\nats$}%
Thus, for all $n,m\in\nats$, $m\mathrel{\pred_\nats}n$ iff $m$ is
exactly one less than $n$. Because ${\pred_\nats}\sub{<}$, and $<$ is
well-founded on $\nats$, Proposition~\ref{WellFoundedSubset} tells us
that $\pred_\nats$ is well-founded on $\nats$. $0$ has no
predecessors in $\pred_\nats$, and, for all $n\in\nats$, $n$ is the
only predecessor of $n+1$ in $\pred_\nats$. Consequently, if a
zero/non-zero case analysis is used, a proof by well-founded induction on
$\pred_\nats$ will look like a proof by mathematical induction.
Suppose $A$ and $B$ are sets, $S$ is a relation on $B$, and $f\in
A\fun B$. Then the \emph{inverse image of the relation} $S$
\emph{under} $f$, $f^{-1}(S)$, is the relation $R$ on $A$ defined
\index{function!inverse image of relation under}%
\index{function! inverse image of relation under@$\cdot^{-1}(\cdot)$}%
\index{ inverse image of relation under@$\cdot^{-1}(\cdot)$}%
by: for all $x,y\in A$, $x\mathrel{R}y$ iff $f\,x\mathrel{S}f\,y$.
\begin{proposition}
\label{InverseImageWellFounded}
Suppose $A$ and $B$ are sets, $S$ is a well-founded relation on $B$,
and $f\in A\fun B$. Then $f^{-1}(S)$ is a well-founded relation on $A$.
\end{proposition}
\begin{proof}
Let $R=f^{-1}(S)$. To see that $R$ is well-founded on $A$, suppose
$X$ is a nonempty subset of $A$. We must show that there is an
$R$-minimal element of $X$. Let $Y=f(X)=\setof{f\,x}{x\in X}$.
Thus $Y$ is a nonempty subset of $B$. Because $S$ is well-founded
on $B$, it follows that there is an $S$-minimal element $y$ of $Y$.
Hence $y=f\,x$ for some $x\in X$.
Suppose, toward a contradiction, that $x$ is not $R$-minimal in $X$.
Thus there is an $x'\in X$ such that $x'\mathrel{R}x$. Hence $f\,x'\in
Y$ and $f\,x'\mathrel{S}f\,x=y$, contradicting the $S$-minimality of
$y$ in $Y$. Thus $x$ is $R$-minimal in $X$.
\end{proof}
For example, let $R$ be the relation on $\ints$ such that, for all
$n,m\in\ints$, $n\mathrel{R}m$ iff $|n|<|m|$ (where we're writing
$|\cdot|$ for the absolute value of an integer). Since $<$ is
well-founded on $\nats$, Proposition~\ref{InverseImageWellFounded}
tells us that $R$ is well-founded on $\ints$. If we do a well-founded
induction on $R$, when proving $P(n)$, for $n\in\ints$, we can make
use of $P(m)$ for any $m\in\ints$ whose absolute value is strictly
less than the absolute value of $n$. E.g., when proving $P(-10)$, we
could make use of $P(5)$ or $P(-9)$.
If $R$ and $S$ are relations on
sets $A$ and $B$, respectively, then the \emph{lexicographic relation of}
\index{relation!well-founded!lexicographic order}%
\index{well-founded relation!lexicographic order}%
\index{relation!well-founded!lexicographic@$\cdot\lex\cdot$}%
\index{well-founded relation!lexicographic@$\cdot\lex\cdot$}%
$R$ \emph{and then} $S$, $R\lex S$, is the relation on $A\times B$ defined
by: $(x,y)\mathrel{R\lex S}(x',y')$ iff
\begin{itemize}
\item $x\mathrel{R}x'$, or
\item $x = x'$ and $y\mathrel{S}y'$.
\end{itemize}
\begin{proposition}
\label{LexWellFounded}
Suppose $R$ and $S$ are well-founded relations on sets $A$ and
$B$, respectively. Then $R\lex S$ is a well-founded relation on
$A\times B$.
\end{proposition}
\begin{proof}
Suppose $T$ is a nonempty subset of $A\times B$. We must show that
there is an $R\lex S$-minimal element of $T$. By our assumption,
$T$ is a relation from $A$ to $B$. Because $T$ is nonempty, it
follows that $\domain\,T$ is a nonempty subset of $A$. Since
$R$ is a well-founded relation on $A$, it follows that there
is an $R$-minimal $x\in\domain\,T$. Let $Y=\setof{y\in B}{(x,y)\in T}$.
Because $Y$ is a nonempty subset of $B$, and
$S$ is well-founded on $B$, there exists an $S$-minimal $y\in Y$.
Thus $(x,y)\in T$.
Suppose, toward a contradiction, that
$(x,y)$ is not $R\lex S$-minimal in $T$. Thus there are
$x'\in A$ and $y'\in B$ such that $(x',y')\in T$ and
$(x',y')\mathrel{R\lex S}(x,y)$. Hence, there are two cases to
consider.
\begin{itemize}
\item Suppose $x'\mathrel{R}x$. Because $x'\in\domain\,T$, this
contradicts the $R$-minimality of $x$ in $\domain\,T$.
\item Suppose $x'=x$ and $y'\mathrel{S}y$. Thus $(x,y')=(x',y')\in T$,
so that $y'\in Y$. But this contradicts the $S$-minimality of $y$
in $Y$.
\end{itemize}
Because we obtained a contradiction in both cases, we have
an overall contradiction. Thus $(x,y)$ is $R\lex S$-minimal in $T$.
\end{proof}
For example, if we consider the strict total ordering $<$ on $\nats$,
then ${<}\lex{<}$ is a well-founded relation on $\nats\times\nats$.
If we do a well-founded induction on ${<}\lex{<}$, when proving that
$P((x,y))$ holds, we can use $P((x',y'))$, whenever $x'<x$ or $x=x'$
but $y'<y$.
Just as we abbreviate $A\times(B\times C)$ to $A\times B\times C$,
and abbreviate $(x,(y,z))$ to $(x,y,z)$, we abbreviate $R\lex(S\lex T)$
to $R\lex S\lex T$.
If $R$, $S$ and $T$ are well-founded relations on sets $A$, $B$ and
$C$, respectively, then $R\lex S\lex T$ is the well-founded relation
on $A\times B\times C$ such that, for all $x\in A$, $y\in B$ and $z\in
C$: $(x,y,z)\mathrel{R\lex S\lex T}(x',y',z')$ iff
\begin{itemize}
\item $x\mathrel{R}x'$, or
\item $x=x'$ and $y\mathrel{S}y'$, or
\item $x=x'$, $y=y'$ and $z\mathrel{T}z'$.
\end{itemize}
And we can do the analogous thing with four or more well-founded
relations.
\index{induction|)}%
\subsection{Notes}
A typical book on formal language theory doesn't introduce well-founded
relations and induction. But this material, and our treatment of
well-founded recursion in the next section, will prove to be useful
in subsequent chapters.
%%% Local Variables:
%%% mode: latex
%%% TeX-master: "book"
%%% End: