forked from fintelkai/fintel-heim-intensional-notes
-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 0
/
Copy path3.Modals.tex
974 lines (795 loc) · 46 KB
/
3.Modals.tex
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
665
666
667
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
675
676
677
678
679
680
681
682
683
684
685
686
687
688
689
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
697
698
699
700
701
702
703
704
705
706
707
708
709
710
711
712
713
714
715
716
717
718
719
720
721
722
723
724
725
726
727
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
735
736
737
738
739
740
741
742
743
744
745
746
747
748
749
750
751
752
753
754
755
756
757
758
759
760
761
762
763
764
765
766
767
768
769
770
771
772
773
774
775
776
777
778
779
780
781
782
783
784
785
786
787
788
789
790
791
792
793
794
795
796
797
798
799
800
801
802
803
804
805
806
807
808
809
810
811
812
813
814
815
816
817
818
819
820
821
822
823
824
825
826
827
828
829
830
831
832
833
834
835
836
837
838
839
840
841
842
843
844
845
846
847
848
849
850
851
852
853
854
855
856
857
858
859
860
861
862
863
864
865
866
867
868
869
870
871
872
873
874
875
876
877
878
879
880
881
882
883
884
885
886
887
888
889
890
891
892
893
894
895
896
897
898
899
900
901
902
903
904
905
906
907
908
909
910
911
912
913
914
915
916
917
918
919
920
921
922
923
924
925
926
927
928
929
930
931
932
933
934
935
936
937
938
939
940
941
942
943
944
945
946
947
948
949
950
951
952
953
954
955
956
957
958
959
960
961
962
963
964
965
966
967
968
969
970
971
972
973
974
%!TEX root = IntensionalSemantics.tex
\excnt=1
\chapter{Modality}\label{cha:modality} % (fold)
\chapterprecishere{We turn to modal auxiliaries and related constructions. We
see more context-dependency. We still quantify over possible worlds.}
\minitoc
\section{The Quantificational Theory of Modality} \label{sec:quant-theory-modal}
We will now be looking at modal auxiliaries like \expression{may, must, can,
have to}, etc. Most of what we say here should carry over straightforwardly to
modal adverbs like \expression{maybe, possibly, certainly}, etc. We will make
certain syntactic assumptions, which make our work easier but which leave aside
many questions that at some point deserve to be addressed.
\clearpage
\subsection{Syntactic Assumptions} \label{sec:synt-assumpt-1}
We will assume, at least for the time being, that a modal like \expression{may}
is a \term{raising} predicate (rather than a \term{control} predicate), i.e.,
its subject is not its own argument, but has been moved from the
subject-position of its infinitival complement.\sidepar{The issue of raising vs.
control will probably be taken up later. If you are eager to get started on it
and other questions of the morphosyntax of modals, read the handout from an
LSA class Sabine and Kai taught a few years ago:
\url{http://web.mit.edu/fintel/lsa220-class-2-handout.pdf}.} So, we are
dealing with the following kind of structure:
\pex
\a Ann may be smart.
\a\null [ Ann [ $\lambda_1$ [ may [ t$_1$ be smart ]]]]
\xe
Actually, we will be working here with the even simpler structure below, in
which the subject has been reconstructed to its lowest trace position. (E.g.,
these could be generated by deleting all but the lowest copy in the movement
chain.\sidepar{We will talk about reconstruction in more detail later.}) We will
be able to prove that movement of a name or pronoun never affects
truth-conditions, so at any rate the interpretation of the structure in (\lastx b)
would be the same as that of (\nextx). As a matter of convenience, then, we will
take the reconstructed structures, which allow us to abstract away from the
(here irrelevant) mechanics of variable binding.
\ex may [ Ann be smart ] \xe
So, for now at least, we are assuming that modals are expressions that take a
full sentence as their semantic argument.\footnote{We will assume that even
though \expression{Ann be smart} is a non-finite sentence, this will not have
any effect on its semantic type, which is that of a sentence, which in turn
means that its semantic value is a truth-value. This is hopefully independent
of the (interesting) fact that \expression{Ann be smart} on its own cannot be
used to make a truth-evaluable assertion.} Now then, what do modals mean?
\subsection{Quantification over Possible Worlds} \label{sec:quant-over-poss}
The\sidepar{This idea goes back a long time. It was famously held by Leibniz,
but there are precedents in the medieval literature; see
\citet{knuuttila:2003:modality-medieval}. See \citet{copeland:2002:genesis}
for the modern history of the possible worlds analysis of modal expressions.}
basic idea of the possible worlds semantics for modal expressions is that they
are quantifiers over possible worlds. Toy lexical entries for \expression{must}
and \expression{may}, for example, would look like this:
\ex $\sv{\mbox{must}}^{w,g} = \lambda p_{\angles{s,t}}.\ \forall w'\co p(w') =
1$. \xe
\ex $\sv{\mbox{may}}^{w,g} = \lambda p_{\angles{s,t}}.\ \exists w'\co p(w') =
1$. \xe
This analysis is too crude (in particular, notice that it would make modal
sentences non-contingent \dash there is no occurrence of the evaluation world on
the right hand side!). But it does already have some desirable consequences that
we will seek to preserve through all subsequent refinements. It correctly
predicts a number of intuitive judgments about the logical relations between
\expression{must} and \expression{may} and among various combinations of these
items and negations. To start with some elementary facts, we feel that
\expression{must} $\phi$ entails \expression{may} $\phi$, but not vice versa:
\ex You must stay.\\
Therefore, you may stay. \hfill\textsc{valid} \xe
\ex You may stay.\\
Therefore, you must stay. \hfill\textsc{invalid} \xe
\pex \a You may stay, but it is not the case that you must stay.\footnote{The
somewhat stilted \expression{it is not the case}-construction is used in (a)
to make certain that negation takes scope over \expression{must}. When modal
auxiliaries and negation are together in the auxiliary complex of the same
clause, their relative scope seems not to be transparently encoded in the
surface order; specifically, the scope order is not reliably negation $\succ$
modal. (Think about examples with \expression{mustn't}, \expression{can't,
shouldn't, may not} etc. What's going on here? This is an interesting topic
which we must set aside for now. See the references at the end of the chapter
for relevant work.) With modal \emph{main} verbs (such as \expression{have
to}), this complication doesn't arise; they are consistently inside the
scope of clause-mate auxiliary negation. Therefore we can use (b) to
(unambiguously) express the same scope order as (a), without having to resort
to a biclausal structure.} \a You may stay, but you don't have to stay.
\hfill\textsc{consistent} \xe
We judge \expression{must} $\phi$ incompatible with its ``inner negation''
\expression{must} [\expression{not} $\phi$ ], but find \expression{may} $\phi$
and \expression{may} [\expression{not} $\phi$ ] entirely compatible:
\ex You must stay, and/but also, you must leave. (leave = not stay).\\
\null\hfill\textsc{contradictory} \xe
\ex You may stay, but also, you may leave. \\
\null\hfill\textsc{consistent} \xe
We also judge that in each pair below, the (a)-sentence and the (b)-sentences
say the same thing.
\pex \a You must stay. \a It is not the case that you may leave.\\
You aren't allowed to leave.\\
(You may not leave.)\footnote{The parenthesized variants of the (b)-sentences are pertinent here only to the extent that we can be certain that negation scopes over the modal. In these examples, apparently it does, but as we remarked above, this cannot be taken for granted in all structures of this form.}\\
(You can't leave.) \xe
\pex \a You may stay. \a It is not the case that you must leave.\\
You don't have to leave.\\
You don't need to leave.\\
(You needn't leave.)
\xe
Given that \expression{stay} and \expression{leave} are each other's negations
(i.e. \exts{leave} = \exts{not stay}, and \exts{stay} = \exts{not leave}), the
LF-structures of these equivalent pairs of sentences can be seen to instantiate
the following schemata:\footnote{In logicians' jargon, \expression{must} and
\expression{may} behave as \term{duals} of each other. For definitions of
``dual'', see \citet[197]{barwise-cooper:1981:generalized} or
\citet[vol.2,238]{gamut:91}.}
\pex \a \expression{must} $\phi$ $\equiv$ \expression{not} [\expression{may}
[\expression{not} $\phi$]] \a \expression{must} [\expression{not}
\ensuremath{\psi}] $\equiv$ \expression{not} [\expression{may}
\ensuremath{\psi}] \xe
\pex \a \expression{may} $\phi$ $\equiv$ \expression{not} [\expression{must}
[\expression{not} $\phi$]] \a \expression{may} [\expression{not}
\ensuremath{\psi}] $\equiv$ \expression{not} [\expression{must}
\ensuremath{\psi}] \xe
Our present analysis of \expression{must}, \expression{have-to}, \dots{} as
universal quantifiers and of \expression{may}, \expression{can}, \dots{} as
existential quantifiers straightforwardly predicts all of the above judgments,
as you can easily prove.\marginnote{More linguistic data regarding the
``parallel logic'' of modals and quantifiers can be found in Larry Horn's
dissertation \citep{horn:1972:dissertation}.}
\pex \a $\forall x \phi \equiv \neg \exists x \neg \phi$ \a $\forall x \neg
\phi \equiv \neg \exists x \phi$ \xe
\pex \a $\exists x \phi \equiv \neg \forall x \neg \phi$ \a $\exists x \neg \phi
\equiv \neg \forall x \phi$ \xe
\section{Flavors of Modality} \label{sec:flavors}
\subsection{Contingency} \label{sec:contingency}
We already said that the semantics we started with is too
simple-minded. In particular, we have no dependency on the evaluation
world, which would make modal statements non-contingent. This is not
correct.
If one says \expression{It may be snowing in Cambridge}, that may well
be part of useful, practical advice about what to wear on your
upcoming trip to Cambridge. It may be true or it may be false. The
sentence seems true if said in the dead of winter when we have already
heard about a Nor'Easter that is sweeping across New England. The
sentence seems false if said by a clueless Australian acquaintance of
ours in July.
The contingency of modal claims is not captured by our current
semantics. All the \expression{may}-sentence would claim under that
semantics is that there is some possible world where it is snowing in
Cambridge. And surely, once you have read Lewis' quote in Chapter 1,
where he asserts the existence of possible worlds with different
physical constants than we enjoy here, you must admit that there have
to be such worlds even if it is July. The problem is that in our
semantics, repeated here
\ex $\sv{\mbox{may}}^{w,g} = \lambda p_{\angles{s,t}}.\ \exists w'\co p(w') =
1$. \xe
there is no occurrence of $w$ on the right hand side. This means that the
truth-conditions for \expression{may}-sentences are world-independent.
In\marginnote{Conversely, the plenitude of possible worlds would make
\expression{must}-claims very likely false if they are not reigned in or
anchored somehow.} other words, they make non-contingent claims that are
either true whatever or false whatever, and because of the plenitude of possible
worlds they are more likely to be true than false. This needs to be fixed. But
how?
Well, what makes \expression{it may be snowing in Cambridge} seem true
when we know about a Nor'Easter over New England? What makes it seem
false when we know that it is summer in New England? The idea is that
we only consider possible worlds \term{compatible with the evidence
available to us}. And since what evidence is available to us differs
from world to world, so will the truth of a
\expression{may}-statement.
\ex $\sv{\mbox{may}}^{w,g} = \lambda p.\ \exists w' \mbox{ compatible with the
evidence in } w\co p(w') = 1$.\footnote{From now on, we will leave off
type-specifications such as that $p$ has to be of type $\angles{s,t}$,
whenever it is obvious what they should be and when saving space is
aesthetically called for.} \xe
\ex $\sv{\mbox{must}}^{w,g} = \lambda p.\ \forall w' \mbox{ compatible with the
evidence in } w\co p(w') = 1$. \xe
Let us consider a different example:
\ex You have to be quiet. \xe
Imagine this sentence being said based on the house rules of the
particular dormitory you live in. Again, this is a sentence that could
be true or could be false. Why do we feel that this is a contingent
assertion? Well, the house rules can be different from one world to
the next, and so we might be unsure or mistaken about what they are.
In one possible world, they say that all noise must stop at 11pm, in
another world they say that all noise must stop at 10pm. Suppose we
know that it is 10:30 now, and that the dorm we are in has either one
or the other of these two rules, but we have forgotten which. Then,
for all we know, \expression{you have to be quiet} may be true or it
may be false. This suggests a lexical entry along these lines:
\ex $\sv{\mbox{have-to}}^{w,g} = \lambda p.\ \forall w' \mbox{ compatible with
the rules in } w\co p(w') = 1$. \xe
Again, we are tying the modal statement about other worlds down to
certain worlds that stand in a certain relation to actual world: those
worlds where the rules as they are here are obeyed.
A note of caution: it is very important to realize that the worlds
compatible with the rules as they are in $w$ are those worlds where
nothing happens that violates any of the $w$-rules. This is not at all
the same as saying that the worlds compatible with the rules in $w$
are those worlds where the same rules are in force. Usually, the rules
do not care what the rules are, unless the rules contain some kind of
meta-statement to the effect that the rules have to be the way they
are, i.e. that the rules cannot be changed. So, in fact, a world $w'$
in which nothing happens that violates the rules as they are in $w$
but where the rules are quite different and in fact what happens
violates the rules as they are in $w'$ is nevertheless a world
compatible with the rules in $w$. For example, imagine that the only
relevant rule in $w$ is that students go to bed before midnight. Take
a world $w'$ where a particular student goes to bed at 11:30 pm but
where the rules are different and say that students have to go to bed
before 11 pm. Such a world $w'$ is compatible with the rules in $w$
(but of course not with the rules in $w'$).
Apparently, there are different flavors of modality, varying in what
kind of facts in the evaluation world they are sensitive to. The
semantics we gave for \expression{must} and \expression{may} above
makes them talk about evidence, while the semantics we gave for
\expression{have-to} made it talk about rules. But that was just
because the examples were hand-picked. In fact, in the dorm scenario
we could just as well have said \expression{You must be quiet}. And,
vice versa, there is nothing wrong with using \expression{it has to be
snowing in Cambridge} based on the evidence we have. In fact, many
modal expressions seem to be multiply ambiguous.
Traditional descriptions of modals often distinguish a number of
``readings'': \term{epistemic, deontic, ability, circumstantial,
dynamic,} \dots. (Beyond ``epistemic'' and ``deontic,'' there is a
great deal of terminological variety. Sometimes all non-epistemic
readings are grouped together under the term \term{root modality}.)
Here are some initial illustrations.
\ex \label{epist}\extitle{Epistemic Modality}\\[6pt]
A: Where is John?\\
B: I don't know. He \expression{may} be at home. \xe
\ex \extitle{Deontic Modality}\\[6pt]
A: Am I allowed to stay over at Janet's house?\\
B: No, but you \expression{may} bring her here for dinner. \xe
\ex \extitle{Circumstantial/Dynamic Modality}\\[6pt]
A: I will plant the rhododendron here.\\
B: That's not a good idea. It \expression{can} grow very tall. \xe
How are \expression{may} and \expression{can} interpreted in each of
these examples? What do the interpretations have in common, and where
do they differ?
In all three examples, the modal makes an existentially quantified
claim about possible worlds. This is usually called the \term{modal
force} of the claim. What differs is what worlds are quantified
over. In \term{epistemic} modal sentences, we quantify over worlds
compatible with the available evidence. In \term{deontic} modal
sentences, we quantify over worlds compatible with the rules and/or
regulations. And in the \term{circumstantial} modal sentence, we
quantify over the set of worlds which conform to the laws of nature
(in particular, plant biology). What speaker B in (\lastx) is saying,
then, is that there are some worlds conforming to the laws of nature
in which this rhododendron grows very tall. (Or is this another
instance of an epistemic reading? See below for discussion of the
distinction between circumstantial readings and epistemic ones.)
How can we account for this variety of readings? One way would be to
write a host of lexical entries, basically treating this as a kind of
(more or less principled) ambiguity. Another
way,\marginpar{\centering\includegraphics[height=1in]{angelika.jpg}\\
{\tiny \href{http://people.umass.edu/kratzer/}{Angelika Kratzer}}}
which is preferred by many people, is to treat this as a case of
context-dependency, as argued in seminal work by
\citet{kratzer:1977:must-can,kratzer:1978:dissertation,kratzer:1981:notional,kratzer:1991:modality}.
According\marginnote{It is well-known that natural language
quantification is in general subject to contextual restriction. See
\citet{stanley-szabo:2000:restriction} for a recent discussion.} to
Kratzer, what a modal brings with it intrinsically is just a modal
force, that is, whether it is an existential (possibility) modal or a
universal (necessity) modal. What worlds it quantifies over is
determined by context. In essence, the context has to supply a
restriction to the quantifier. How can we implement this idea?
We encountered context-dependency before when we talked about pronouns and their
referential (and E-Type) readings (H\amp K, chapters 9--11). We treated
referential pronouns as free variables, appealing to a general principle that
free variables in an LF need to be supplied with values from the utterance
context. If we want to describe the context-dependency of modals in a
technically analogous fashion, we can think of their LF-representations as
incorporating or subcategorizing for a kind of invisible pronoun, a free
variable that stands for a set of possible worlds.
So\sidepar{\textbf{Warning}: This account is problematic and will be refined
soon.} we posit LF-structures like this:
\ex \label{newlf} [I$'$ [I must $p_{\angles{n,\angles{s,t}}}$ ] [VP you quiet]] \xe
\sidepar{We are using the notation for variables of types other than
$e$ introduced by Heim \amp\ Kratzer. See p. 213. An index on a
variable now is an ordered pair of a natural number and a type.
\\[\baselineskip] Q: Can you think of overt anaphoric expressions
that are arguably of the type $\angles{s,t}$, a proposition?}%
$p_{\angles{n,\angles{s,t}}}$ here is a variable over (characteristic
functions of) sets of worlds, which \dash like all free variables
\dash needs to receive a value from the utterance context. Possible
values include: the set of worlds compatible with the speaker's
current knowledge; the set of worlds in which everyone obeys all the
house rules of a certain dormitory; and many others. The denotation of
the modal itself now has to be of type $\angles{st,\angles{st,t}}$
rather than $\angles{st,t}$, thus it will be more like a
quantificational determiner rather than a complete generalized
quantifier. Only after the modal has been combined with its covert
restrictor do we obtain a value of type $\angles{st,t}$.
\pex \a \exts{must} = \exts{have-to} = \exts{need-to} = \dots{} =\\
$\lambda p\in D_{\angles{s,t}}.\ \lambda q\in D_{\angles{s,t}}.\ \forall w\in W\ [p(w)=1 \rightarrow q(w)=1]$\marginnote{in set talk: $p\ensuremath{\subseteq}q$}
\a \exts{may} = \exts{can} = \exts{be-allowed-to} = \dots{} =\\
$\lambda p\in D_{\angles{s,t}}.\ \lambda q\in D_{\angles{s,t}}.\ \exists w\in W\
[p(w)=1\ \&\ q(w)=1]$\marginnote{in set talk:
$p\ensuremath{\cap}q\ensuremath{\neq}\ensuremath{\emptyset}$} \xe
On this approach, the epistemic, deontic, etc. ``readings'' of
individual occurrences of modal verbs come about by a combination of
two separate things. The lexical semantics of the modal itself encodes
just a quantificational force, a \emph{relation} between sets of
worlds. This is either the subset-relation (universal quantification;
necessity) or the relation of non-disjointness (existential
quantification; possibility). The covert variable next to the modal
picks up a contextually salient set of worlds, and this functions as
the quantifier's restrictor. The labels ``epistemic'', ``deontic'',
``circumstantial'' etc. group together certain conceptually natural
classes of possible values for this covert restrictor.
Notice that, strictly speaking, there is not just one deontic reading
(for example), but many. A speaker who utters
\ex You have to be quiet. \xe
might mean: `I want you to be quiet,' (i.e., you are quiet in all
those worlds that conform to my preferences). Or she might mean:
`unless you are quiet, you won't succeed in what you are trying to
do,' (i.e., you are quiet in all those worlds in which you succeed at
your current task). Or she might mean: `the house rules of this
dormitory here demand that you be quiet,' (i.e., you are quiet in all
those worlds in which the house rules aren't violated). And so on. So
the label ``deontic'' appears to cover a whole open-ended set of
imaginable ``readings'', and which one is intended and understood on a
particular utterance occasion may depend on all sorts of things in the
interlocutors' previous conversation and tacit shared assumptions.
(And the same goes for the other traditional labels.)
\subsection{Epistemic vs. Circumstantial Modality}
Is it all context-dependency? Or do flavors of modality correspond to
some sorts of signals in the structure of sentences? Read the
following famous passage from Kratzer and think about how the two
sentences with their very different modal meanings differ in
structure:
\begin{quote}
Consider\marginnote{Quoted from \citet{kratzer:1991:modality}. In
\citet{kratzer:1981:notional}, the hydrangeas were
\expression{Zwetschgenbäume} `plum trees'. The German word
\expression{Zwetschge}, by the way, is etymologically derived from
the name of the city Damascus (Syria), the center of the ancient
plum trade.} sentences (\nextx) and (\anextx):
\ex Hydrangeas can grow here. \xe
\ex There might be hydrangeas growing here. \xe
The two sentences differ in meaning in a way which is illustrated by
the following scenario.
\medskip ``Hydrangeas''
\medskip Suppose I acquire a piece of land in a far away country and
discover that soil and climate are very much like at home, where
hydrangeas prosper everywhere. Since hydrangeas are my favorite
plants, I wonder whether they would grow in this place and inquire
about it. The answer is (\blastx). In such a situation, the proposition
expressed by (\blastx) is true. It is true regardless of whether it is
or isn't likely that there are already hydrangeas in the country we
are considering. All that matters is climate, soil, the special
properties of hydrangeas, and the like. Suppose now that the country
we are in has never had any contacts whatsoever with Asia or
America, and the vegetation is altogether different from ours. Given
this evidence, my utterance of (\lastx) would express a false
proposition. What counts here is the complete evidence available.
And this evidence is not compatible with the existence of
hydrangeas.
\medskip (\blastx) together with our scenario illustrates the pure
\term{circumstantial} reading of the modal \expression{can}. [\dots
]. (\lastx) together with our scenario illustrates the epistemic
reading of modals. [\dots] circumstantial and epistemic
conversational backgrounds involve different kinds of facts. In
using an epistemic modal, we are interested in what else may or must
be the case in our world given all the evidence available. Using a
circumstantial modal, we are interested in the necessities implied
by or the possibilities opened up by certain sorts of facts.
Epistemic modality is the modality of curious people like
historians, detectives, and futurologists. Circumstantial modality
is the modality of rational agents like gardeners, architects, and
engineers. A historian asks what might have been the case, given all
the available facts. An engineer asks what can be done given certain
relevant facts.
\end{quote}
\noindent Consider also the very different prominent meanings of the
following two sentences, taken from Kratzer as well:
\pex \a Cathy can make a pound of cheese out of this can of milk.
\a Cathy might make a pound of cheese out of this can of milk. \xe
\begin{exercise}
Come up with examples of epistemic, deontic, and circumstantial uses
of the necessity verb \expression{have to}. Describe the set of
worlds that constitutes the understood restrictor in each of your
examples. \eex
\end{exercise}
\subsection{Contingency Again}
We messed up. If you inspect the context-dependent meanings we have on
the table now for our modals, you will see that the right hand sides
again do not mention the evaluation world $w$. Therefore, we will
again have the problem of not making contingent claims, indirectly
about the actual world. This needs to be fixed. We need a semantics
that is both context-dependent and contingent.
The problem, it turns out, is with the idea that the utterance context
supplies a \emph{determinate set of worlds} as the restrictor. When I
understand that you meant your use of \expression{must}, in
\expression{you must be quiet}, to quantify over the set of worlds in
which the house rules of our dorm are obeyed, this does not imply that
you and I have to know or agree on which set exactly this is. That
depends on what the house rules in our world actually happen to say,
and this may be an open question at the current stage of our
conversation. What we do agree on, if I have understood your use of
\expression{must} in the way that you intended it, is just that it
quantifies over \emph{whatever set of worlds it may be} that the house
rules pick out.
The technical implementation of this
%\marginnote{You will of
% course recognize that functions of type $\angles{s,st}$ are simply a
% schönfinkeled version of the \term{accessibility relations} we
% introduced in the previous chapter.}
insight requires that we think
of the context's contribution not as a set of worlds, but rather as a
function which for each world it applies to picks out such a set. For
example, it may be the function which, for any world $w$, yields the
set \{$w'$: the house rules that are in force in $w$ are obeyed in
$w'$\}. If we apply this function to a world $w_{1}$, in which the
house rules read ``no noise after 10 pm'', it will yield a set of
worlds in which nobody makes noise after 10 pm. If we apply the same
function to a world $w_{2}$, in which the house rules read ``no noise
after 11 pm'', it will yield a set of worlds in which nobody makes
noise after 11 pm.
Suppose, then, that the covert restrictor of a modal predicate denotes
such a function, i.e., its value is of type $\angles{s,st}$.
\ex \label{newnewlf} [I' [I must $R_{\angles{n,\angles{s,st}}}$ ] [VP you
quiet]] \xe
And the new lexical entries for \expression{must} and \expression{may}
that will fit this new structure are these:
\pex \a \exts{must} = \exts{have-to} = \exts{need-to} = \dots{} =\\
$\lambda R\in D_{\angles{s,st}}.\ \lambda q\in D_{\angles{s,t}}.\ \forall w'\in W\ [R(w)(w') =1 \rightarrow q(w')=1]$\marginnote{in set talk: $R(w)\ensuremath{\subseteq}q$}
\a \exts{may} = \exts{can} = \exts{be-allowed-to} = \dots{} =\\
$\lambda R\in D_{\angles{s,st}}.\ \lambda q\in D_{\angles{s,t}}.\ \exists w'\in
W\ [R(w)(w')=1\ \&\ q(w')=1]$\marginnote{in set talk:
$R(w)\ensuremath{\cap}q\ensuremath{\neq}\ensuremath{\emptyset}$} \xe
%
Let us see now how this solves the contingency problem.
\ex Let $w$ be a world, and assume that the context supplies an assignment $g$ such that $g(R_{\angles{17,\angles{s,st}}}) = \lambda w.\ \lambda w'.$ the house rules in force in $w$ are obeyed in $w'$\\[9pt]
\exts{must $R_{\angles{17,\angles{s,st}}}$ you quiet} = \\
\exts{must $R_{\angles{17,\angles{s,st}}}$}$(\lambda w'\ $\exts[w']{you quiet}) = \\
\exts{must} (\exts{$R_{\angles{17,\angles{s,st}}}$}) $(\lambda w'\ $\exts[w']{you quiet}) = \\
\exts{must} (\exts{$R_{\angles{17,\angles{s,st}}}$}) $(\lambda w'.\ $you are quiet in $w'$) = \\
$\forall w'\in W\co$ \exts{$R_{\angles{17,\angles{s,st}}}$}$(w)(w') =1 \rightarrow $ you are quiet
in $w'$ = 1 iff\\
$\forall w'\in W\co$ $g$({$R_{\angles{17,\angles{s,st}}}$})$(w)(w') =1 \rightarrow $ you are quiet
in $w'$ = 1 iff \\
$\forall w'\in W$ [the house rules in force in $w$ are obeyed in $w'$ \\
\null\hfill $\rightarrow$ you are quiet in $w'$] \xe
%
As we see in the last line of (\lastx), the truth-value of (\ref{newnewlf})
depends on the evaluation world $w$.
\begin{exercise}
Describe two worlds $w_{1}$ and $w_{2}$ so that\\
\exts[w_1,g]{must $R_{\angles{17,\angles{s,st}}}$ you quiet} = 1 and \exts[w_2,g]{must $R_{\angles{17,\angles{s,st}}}$ you quiet} = 0. \eex
\end{exercise}
\begin{exercise}
In analogy to the deontic relation
$g(R_{\angles{17,\angles{s,st}}})$ defined in (\lastx), define an
appropriate relation that yields an epistemic reading for a sentence
like \expression{You may be quiet}. \eex
\end{exercise}
\subsection{Iteration}
Consider the following example:
\ex You might have to leave. \xe
What does this mean? Under one natural interpretation, we learn that
the speaker considers it possible that the addressee is under the
obligation to leave. This seems to involve one modal embedded under a
higher modal. %
\sidepar{There is more to be said about which modals can embed under
which other modals. See for some discussion the handout mentioned
earlier:
\url{http://web.mit.edu/fintel/lsa220-class-2-handout.pdf}.}%
It appears that this sentence should be true in a world $w$ iff some
world $w'$ compatible with what the speaker knows in $w$ is such that
every world $w''$ in which the rules as they are in $w'$ are followed
is such that you leave in $w''$.
Assume the following LF:
\ex\null [I$'$ [ might $R_{\angles{1,\angles{s,st}}}$] [VP [ have-to
$R_{\angles{2,\angles{s,st}}}$] [IP you leave]]] \xe
Suppose $w$ is the world for which we calculate the truth-value of %
\sidepar{From now on, we will omit the type-designation of variables
whenever we feel confident that their type is easy to figure out
from the context.}%
the whole sentence, and the context maps $R_1$ to the function which maps
$w$ to the set of all those worlds compatible with what is known in
$w$. \expression{might} says that some of those worlds are worlds $w'$
that make the tree below \expression{might} true. Now assume further
that the context maps $R_2$ to the function which assigns to any such
world $w'$ the set of all those worlds in which the rules as they are
in $w'$ are followed. \expression{have to} says that all of those
worlds are worlds $w''$ in which you leave.
In other words, while it is not known to be the case that you have to
leave, for all the speaker knows it might be the case.
\begin{exercise}
Describe values for the covert \angles{s,st}-variable that are
intuitively suitable for the interpretation of the modals in the
following sentences:
\ex As far as John's preferences are concerned, you
\expression{may} stay with us. \xe
\ex According to the guidelines of the graduate school, every PhD
candidate \expression{must} take 9 credit hours outside his/her
department. \xe
\ex John \expression{can} run a mile in 5 minutes. \xe
\ex This \expression{has} to be the White House. \xe
\ex This elevator \expression{can} carry up to 3000 pounds. \xe
For some of the sentences, different interpretations are conceivable
depending on the circumstances in which they are uttered. You may
therefore have to sketch the utterance context you have in mind
before describing the accessibility relation. \eex
\end{exercise}
\begin{exercise}
Collect two naturally occurring examples of modalized sentences
(e.g., sentences that you overhear in conversation, or read in a
newspaper or novel -- not ones that are being used as examples in a
linguistics or philosophy paper!), and give definitions of values
for the covert \angles{s,st}-variable which account for the way in
which you actually understood these sentences when you encountered
them. (If the appropriate interpretation is not salient for the
sentence out of context, include information about the relevant
preceding text or non-linguistic background.) \eex
\end{exercise}
\section{Supplemental Readings} \label{sec:suppl-read-modals}
{\setlength{\parindent}{0pt}\setlength{\parskip}{6pt}
The most important background readings for this chapter are the
following two papers by Kratzer:
\begin{bibentrylist}
\item \bibentry{kratzer:1981:notional}.
\item \bibentry{kratzer:1991:modality}.
\end{bibentrylist}
There are updated versions of Kratzer's classic papers in her volume ``Modals
and conditionals''
(\url{https://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199234684.001.0001}).
A major new resource on modality is Paul Portner's book:
\begin{bibentrylist}
\item\bibentry{portner:2009:modality-book}.
\end{bibentrylist}
You might also profit from other survey-ish type papers:
\begin{bibentrylist}
\item \bibentry{fintel:2005:modality}.
\item \bibentry{fintel-gillies:2007:ose2}.
\item \bibentry{swanson:2008:modality}.
\item \bibentry{hacquard:2009:hsk-modality}.
\end{bibentrylist}
On the syntax of modals, there are only a few papers of uneven
quality. Some of the more recent work is listed here. Follow up on
older references from the bibliographies in these papers.
\begin{bibentrylist}
\item \bibentry{bhatt:1997:haveto}.
\item \bibentry{wurmbrand:1999:raising}.
\item \bibentry{cormack-smith:2002:modals}.
\item \bibentry{butler:2003:modality}.
\end{bibentrylist}
The following paper explores some issues in the LF-syntax of epistemic
modals:
\begin{bibentrylist}
\item \bibentry{fintel-iatridou:2003:ec}.
\end{bibentrylist}
Valentine Hacquard's MIT dissertation is a rich source of
cross-linguistic issues in modality, as is Fabrice Nauze's Amsterdam
dissertation:
\begin{bibentrylist}
\item \bibentry{hacquard:2006:dissertation}.
\item \bibentry{nauze:2008:thesis}.
\end{bibentrylist}
Some more recent work by Hacquard deals with deriving and correlating modal
flavors with syntactic position of the modal auxiliaries:
\begin{bibentrylist}
\item \bibentry{hacquard-2010-event-relativity}.
\item \bibentry{hacquard-2013-modality}.
\end{bibentrylist}
A recent handbook article by Hacquard on actuality entailments (involving the
interaction of modality with aspect; we'll discuss aspect later in these notes):
\begin{bibentrylist}
\item \bibentry{hacquard-2016-actuality}.
\end{bibentrylist}
The semantics of epistemic modals has become a hot topic recently.
Here are some of the main references:
\begin{bibentrylist}
\item \bibentry{hacking:1967:possibility}.
\item \bibentry{teller:1972:epistemic}.
\item \bibentry{derose:1991:epistemic}.
\item \bibentry{egan-hawthorne-weatherson:2005:epistemic}.
\item \bibentry{egan:2007:epistemic}.
\item \bibentry{macfarlane:2006:might}.
\item \bibentry{stephenson:2007:judge-lp}.
\item \bibentry{hawthorne:2007:danger}.
\item \bibentry{fintel-gillies:2008:cia-leaks}.
\item \bibentry{fintel-gillies:2008:mmr}.
\end{bibentrylist}
A paper by Pranav Anand and Valentine Hacquard tackles what happens to epistemic
modals under attitude predicates:
\begin{bibentrylist}
\item \bibentry{anand-hacquard-2013-epistemic-attitudes}.
\end{bibentrylist}
Evidentiality is a topic closely related to epistemic modality. Some
references:
\begin{bibentrylist}
\item \bibentry{willett:1988:evidentials}.
\item \bibentry{aikhenvald:2004:evidentiality}.
\item \bibentry{drubig:2001:epistemic}.
\item \bibentry{blain-dechaine:2007:evidentials}.
\item \bibentry{mccready-ogata:2007:evidentials}.
\item \bibentry{speas:2008:evidentials}.
\item \bibentry{fintel-gillies:2010:mss}.
\end{bibentrylist}
Modals interact with disjunction and indefinites to generate so-called
\term{free choice}-readings, which are a perennial puzzle. Here is
just a very small set of initial references:
\begin{bibentrylist}
\item \bibentry{kamp:1973:freechoice}.
\item \bibentry{zimmermann:2000:fc-disjunction}.
\item \bibentry{schulz:2005:fcp-synthese}.
\item \bibentry{aloni:2007:freechoice}.
\item \bibentry{alonso-ovalle:2006:thesis}.
\item \bibentry{fox:2007:freechoice}.
\item \bibentry{rooij:2006:donkeys}.
\end{bibentrylist}
}
% Additional material; may fit in later
% \subsection{A technical variant of the analysis}\label{techvariant}
% In our account of the contingency of modalized sentences, we adopted
% lexical entries for the modals that gave them world-dependent
% extensions of type \angles{\angles{s,st}, \angles{st,t}}:
% \ex (repeated from earlier):\\
% For any $w \in W$: \exts{must}\\
% $\lambda R\in D_{\angles{s,st}}.\ \lambda q\in D_{\angles{s,t}}.\ \forall w'\in W\ [R(w)(w') =1 \rightarrow q(w')=1]$\\
% \null\hfill(in set talk: $\lambda R_{\angles{s,st}}.\ \lambda q_{\angles{s,t}}.\
% R(w)\ensuremath{\subseteq}q$). \xe
% Unfortunately, this treatment somewhat obscures the parallel between
% the modals and the quantificational determiners, which have
% world-independent extensions of type \angles{et, \angles{et,t}}.
% Let's explore an alternative solution to the contingency problem,
% which will allow us to stick with the world-independent
% type-\angles{st,\angles{st,t}}-extensions that we assumed for the
% modals at first:
% \ex (repeated from even earlier): \\
% \exts{must} = $\lambda p\in D_{\angles{s,t}}.\ \lambda q\in D_{\angles{s,t}}.\ \forall w\in W\ [p(w)=1 \rightarrow q(w)=1]$\\
% \null\hfill(in set talk: $\lambda p \in D_{\angles{s,t}}.\ \lambda q \in
% D_{\angles{s,t}}.\ p \ensuremath{\subseteq} q$). \xe
% We posit the following LF-representation:
% \ex \label{brandlf} [I$'$ [I must [ $R_{\angles{4,\angles{s,st}}}\ w*$]] [VP you
% quiet]] \xe
% What is new here is that the covert restrictor is complex The first
% part, $R_{\angles{4,\angles{s,st}}}$, is (as before) a free variable
% of type \angles{s,st}, which gets assigned an accessibility relation
% by the context of utterance. %
% \sidepar{Note that as soon as we're introducing an object language
% expression whose extension is a possible world, we will now have
% expressions of type $s$ and should also introduce the domain of
% things of type $s$: $D_s = W$.}%
% The second part is a special terminal symbol which is interpreted as
% picking out the evaluation world:
% \ex For any $w\in W: \sv{w*}^{w,g} =
% w$.\footnote{\citet{dowty:1982:time-adverbs} introduced an analogous symbol to
% pick out the evaluation \emph{time}. We have chosen the star-notation to
% allude to this precedent.} \xe
% When $R_{\angles{4,\angles{s,st}}}$ and $w*$ combine (by
% Functional Application), we obtain a constituent whose extension is of
% type \angles{s,t} (a proposition or set of worlds). This is the same
% type as the extension of the free variable $p$ in the previous
% proposal, hence suitable to combine with the old entry for
% \expression{must} (by FA). However, while the extension of $p$ was
% completely fixed by the variable assignment, and did not vary with the
% evaluation world, the new complex constituent's extension depends on
% both the assignment and the world:
% \ex For any $w\in W$ and any assignment $g$: \\
% \exts[w,g]{$R_{\angles{4,\angles{s,st}}}\ w*$} =
% g(\angles{4,\angles{s,st}})($w$). \xe
% As a consequence of this, the extensions of the higher nodes I and
% I$'$ will also vary with the evaluation world, and this is how we
% capture the fact that \ref{brandlf} is contingent.
% Maybe this variant is more appealing. But for the rest of this
% chapter, we continue to assume the original analysis as presented
% earlier. %In the next chapter on conditionals, we will however make
% %crucial use of this way of formulating the semantics for modals.
% Nevertheless, make sure you understand what we just proposed, since it may turn
% out to be useful.
% \section{*Kratzer's Conversational Backgrounds} \label{sec:kratz-conv-backgr}
% Angelika Kratzer has some interesting ideas on how accessibility
% relations are supplied by the context. She argues that what is really
% floating around in a discourse is a \term{conversational background}.
% Accessibility relations can be computed from conversational
% backgrounds (as we shall do here), or one can state the semantics of
% modals directly in terms of conversational backgrounds (as Kratzer
% does).
% A conversational background is the sort of thing that is identified by
% phrases like \expression{what the law provides, what we know}, etc.
% Take the phrase \expression{what the law provides}. What the law
% provides is different from one possible world to another. And what the
% law provides in a particular world is a \emph{set of propositions}.
% Likewise, what we know differs from world to world. And what we know
% in a particular world is a set of propositions. The intension of
% \expression{what the law provides} is then that function which assigns
% to every possible world the set of propositions $p$ such that the law
% provides in that world that $p$. Of course, that doesn't mean that $p$
% holds in that world itself: the law can be broken. And the intension
% of \expression{what we know} will be that function which assigns to
% every possible world the set of propositions we know in that world.
% Quite generally, conversational backgrounds are functions of type
% \angles{s,\angles{st,t}}, functions from worlds to (characteristic
% functions of) sets of propositions.
% Now, consider:
% \ex (In view of what we know,) Brown must have murdered Smith. \xe
% The \expression{in view of}-phrase may explicitly signal the intended
% conversational background. Or, if the phrase is omitted, we can just
% infer from other clues in the discourse that such an epistemic
% conversational background is intended. We will focus on the case of
% pure context-dependency.
% How do we get from a conversational background to an accessibility
% relation? Take the conversational background at work in (\lastx). It will
% be the following:
% \ex $\lambda w.\ \lambda p.\ p$ is one of the propositions that we know in $w$. \xe
% This conversational background will assign to any world $w$ the set of
% propositions $p$ that in $w$ are known by us. So we have a set of
% propositions. From that we can get the set of worlds in which all of
% the propositions in this set are true. These are the worlds that are
% compatible with everything we know. So, this is how we get an
% accessibility relation:
% \ex \label{convers} For any conversational background f of type \angles{s,\angles{st,t}}, we define the corresponding accessibility relation $R_{f}$ of type \angles{s,st} as follows: \\
% $R_{f} := \lambda w.\ \lambda w'.\ \forall p\ [ f(w)(p)=1\ \rightarrow\ p(w')=1
% ]$. \xe
% \enlargethispage{24pt}In words, $w'$ is $f$-accessible from $w$ iff all propositions $p$ that are assigned by $f$ to $w$ are true in $w'$.
% Kratzer uses the term \term{modal base} for the conversational
% background that determines the set of accessible worlds. We can be
% sloppy and use this term for a number of interrelated concepts:
% \begin{enumerate}[(i)]
% \item the conversational background (type \angles{s,\angles{st,t}}),
% \item the set of propositions assigned by the conversational
% background to a particular world (type \angles{st,t}),
% \item the accessibility relation (type \angles{s,st}) determined by (i),
% \item the set of worlds accessible from a particular world (type \angles{s,t}).
% \end{enumerate}
% \noindent Kratzer calls a conversational background (modal base)
% \term{realistic} iff it assigns to \emph{any} world a set of
% propositions that are all true in that world. The modal base
% \expression{what we know} is realistic, the modal bases
% \expression{what we believe} and \expression{what we want} are not.
% \medskip
% \noindent What follows are some (increasingly technical exercises) on
% conversational backgrounds.
% \begin{exercise}
% Show that a conversational background $f$ is realistic iff the
% corresponding accessibility relation $R_{f}$ (defined as in (\lastx))
% is reflexive. \eex
% \end{exercise}
% \begin{exercise}
% Let us call an accessibility relation \term{trivial} if it makes
% every world accessible from every world. $R$ is \term{trivial} iff
% $\forall w\forall w'\!:\ w'\in R(w)$. What would the conversational
% background $f$ have to be like for the accessibility relation
% $R_{f}$ to be trivial in this sense? \eex
% \end{exercise}
% \begin{exercise}\label{closure}
% The definition in (\lastx) specifies, in effect, a function from
% $D_{\angles{s,\angles{st,t}}}$ to $D_{\angles{s,st}}$. It maps each
% function $f$ of type \angles{s,\angles{st,t}} to a unique function
% $R_{f}$ of type \angles{s,st}. This mapping is not one-to-one,
% however. Different elements of $D_{\angles{s,\angles{st,t}}}$ may be
% mapped to the same value in $D_{\angles{s,st}}$.\footnote{In this
% exercise, we systematically substitute sets for their
% characteristic functions. I.e., we pretend that $D_{\angles{s,t}}$
% is the power set of $W$ (i.e., elements of $D_{\angles{s,t}}$ are
% sets of worlds), and $D_{\angles{st,t}}$ is the power set of
% $D_{\angles{s,t}}$ (i.e., elements of $D_{\angles{st,t}}$ are sets
% of sets of worlds). On these assumptions, the definition in (\lastx)
% can take the following form:
% \ex For any conversational background $f$ of type \angles{s,\angles{st,t}}, \\
% we define the corresponding accessibility relation $R_{f}$ of type \angles{s,st} as follows:\\
% $R_{f} := \lambda w.\ \{w'\co\ \forall p\ [p\in f(w)\ \rightarrow\ w'\in p]
% \}$. \xe
% The last line of this can be further abbreviated to:
% \ex $R_{f} := \lambda w.\ \ensuremath{\cap}f(w)$ \xe
% This formulation exploits a set-theoretic notation which we have
% also used in condition \refx{ex:bigcap} of the second part of the exercise.
% It is defined as follows:
% \ex If $S$ is a set of sets, then $\ensuremath{\cap}S\ :=\ \{x\co\ \forall Y\
% [Y\in S\ \rightarrow\ x\in Y]\}$. \xe
% }
% \begin{itemize}
% \item Prove this claim. I.e., give an example of two functions f and
% f' in $D_{\angles{s,\angles{st,t}}}$ for which (\lastx) determines
% $R_{f}$ = $R_{f'}$ .
% \item As you have just proved, if every function of type
% \angles{s,\angles{st,t}} qualifies as a `conversational
% background', then two different conversational backgrounds can
% collapse into the same accessibility relation. Conceivably,
% however, if we imposed further restrictions on conversational
% backgrounds (i.e., conditions by which only a proper subset of the
% functions in $D_{\angles{s,\angles{st,t}}}$ would qualify as
% conversational backgrounds), then the mapping between
% conversational backgrounds and accessibility relations might
% become one-to-one after all. In this light, consider the following
% potential restriction:
% \ex Every conversational background $f$ must be ``closed under entailment''; i.e., it must meet this condition:\\
% $\forall w. \forall p\ [ \ensuremath{\cap}f(w) \ensuremath{\subseteq} p\
% \rightarrow\ p \in f(w) ]$.\label{ex:bigcap} \xe
% (In words: if the propositions in $f(w)$ taken together entail
% $p$, then $p$ must itself be in $f(w)$.) Show that this
% restriction would ensure that the mapping defined in (\blastx) will
% be one-to-one. \eex
% \end{itemize}
% \end{exercise}